Metaphysics: The Last Stronghold of Aristotle

作者:中国现代哲学家学会
发表时间:
+-


Metaphysics: The Last Stronghold of Aristotle Needs a Rebirth


For over two thousand years, Aristotle's metaphysics stood as the towering edifice of Western philosophical thought. It was not merely a contribution; it was a foundation. From his "four causes" to the classification of substance and accident, from his logic to his concept of the unmoved mover, Aristotle offered a framework that ordered the world of knowledge, provided scaffolding for medieval theology, and silently shaped modern science’s early rational structure. Yet today, this proud structure—so deeply ingrained in our intellectual DNA—finds itself out of joint with reality. Not because it was wrong in its time, but because reality itself has changed, or rather, our access to its structure has matured.


The final stronghold of Aristotle—metaphysics—now calls not for renovation, but for rebirth. We are not merely updating ancient categories; we are witnessing a categorical shift, a paradigm realignment that necessitates a new language, a new structure, and a new metaphysical vision. That vision, in part, is emerging through Instancology, a structured philosophical system that replaces the static with the dynamic, the substantial with the instantiative, the teleological with the relational.


I. Why Aristotle’s Metaphysics Once Reigned Supreme


Aristotle's metaphysics was a grand synthesis of order. He divided reality into substances and their properties, saw causes as fourfold (material, formal, efficient, and final), and grounded being in actuality and potentiality. Everything had its place, its nature, and its end. His logic—syllogistic, deductive—provided tools to make sense of it all.


More importantly, Aristotle's metaphysics wasn’t isolated. It governed biology, cosmology, ethics, and politics. Thomas Aquinas used it to define God; Islamic philosophers adapted it to understand creation; early scientists borrowed its clarity. Its comprehensiveness was its power.


But that power came at a price. It required stability. Essences had to be fixed, causes identifiable, the cosmos intelligible in hierarchical terms. That vision—cosmic, structured, deterministic—was deeply suited


That vision—cosmic, structured, deterministic—was deeply suited to a world that seemed still, ordered, and divine. But once the microscope, telescope, and calculus cracked open the fabric of matter and motion, cracks also began appearing in the Aristotelian edifice. The Copernican revolution displaced Earth from the center. The Cartesian method severed substance from certainty. Newton’s laws made efficient causality central, while Hume cast doubt on causation itself. By the time Kant and Heidegger came on stage, metaphysics was no longer a stage of certainty, but a site of existential questioning.


Still, Aristotle endured—less as a doctrine, more as a shadow. His assumptions lingered in notions of identity, essence, subject, and object. Even postmodern critiques rarely escaped the foundational logic he laid down. As long as metaphysics remained about “what is,” about beings and their categories, Aristotle’s ghost remained enthroned.


But the 21st century demands more than critique. It demands reconstruction. Not of Aristotle’s house, but of metaphysics itself—from its foundation upward.



---


II. Why Metaphysics Must Be Reborn, Not Revised


To speak of metaphysics today is to risk obsolescence. In an era obsessed with data, computation, and functionalism, metaphysics is dismissed as speculative luxury. But this dismissal misses the point. What needs rejection is not metaphysics per se, but its outdated structure—its metaphysical model of metaphysics.


What is this outdated model? First, it is based on substance ontology: that things exist because they are something in themselves. Second, it relies on categorical fixity: that things possess essences, and relations are secondary. Third, it is teleological: explaining the world by its ends, goals, or functions. Finally, it privileges a top-down causal scheme rooted in the visible, measurable, and pre-defined.


This model fails to accommodate today’s discoveries:


Quantum indeterminacy undermines stable substance and fixed cause.


Complex systems theory shows emergence from bottom-up relations.


Neuroscience and AI challenge the notion of a self-contained “self” or “soul.”


Linguistic and cultural relativism question the fixity of meaning and identity.



In short, reality has become dynamic, instantiated, relational, and layered. The very conditions under which Aristotle's metaphysics thrived—conceptual clarity, fixed ontologies, and logical deduction—are now inadequate. What we need is not a renovation of metaphysics, but its rebirth under new philosophical conditions.



---


III. Enter Instancology: The Structured Rebirth of Metaphysics


Instancology does not negate metaphysics—it rescues it from static decay and rebirths it through structure. Where Aristotle saw being as substance and essence, Instancology sees instance as the fundamental unit of reality—not static being, but instantiation within relational fields.


At the heart of Instancology is a 2x2 ontological framework:


AA (Absolutely Absolute): The source, unchanging and issuing all reality—timeless.


RA (Relatively Absolute): Entities like logic, law, math, and life—formless but absolute within this instance.


AR (Absolutely Relative): The experienced world, filtered through categories of meaning and cognition.


RR (Relatively Relative): The purely relational, contextual, and symbolic—language, culture, opinion.



This layered structure replaces the rigid hierarchy of Aristotle with a matrix of relation, cognition, and issuance. There is no substance beneath phenomena, only instances—structured manifestations issued from AA into the relational field of AR and RR, mediated by RA. The world is not being but instancing. Not essence but structured appearance grounded in metaphysical issuance.


Instancology, thus, redefines metaphysics in four essential ways:


1. From Substance to Instance: There are no eternal substances; only structured manifestations within one issued instance.



2. From Essence to Issuance: Reality is not grounded in inner essences but in the issuing act of AA.



3. From Fixed Categories to Relational Layers: Reality is layered by how it appears (RR), how it is cognitively structured (AR), how it is logically and lawfully governed (RA), and how it ultimately comes to be (AA).



4. From Teleology to Meta-Structure: Ends no longer define existence. Instead, structure does. Relations, cognition, and issuance form the true scaffolding of metaphysical order.





---


IV. Why This Rebirth Matters Now


The consequences of metaphysical stagnation are not merely academic. Our civilizational paralysis—ethical confusion, technological alienation, political cynicism—reflects an underlying metaphysical vacuum. If reality is not knowable in structure, then we drift among opinions. If identity is not grounded in something deeper than symbol or desire, then subjectivity becomes a game of masks. If truth is not mapped within a structured metaphysical field, then science floats without foundation, and ethics without direction.


Instancology returns structure to metaphysics—but without regression. It re-establishes an absolute (AA) without dogma, reaffirms reason (RA) without rationalism, recasts appearance (AR) without illusion, and orders relation (RR) without reduction.


This is not a revision of Aristotle—it is his overcoming. Instancology honors the ambition of metaphysics, but sheds its ancient skin. It gives us a new language for what is ultimate, a new scaffold for understanding, and a new metaphysical grammar fit for a structured, dynamic, post-substantial world.



---


V. Conclusion: From the Last Stronghold to the First Portal


Aristotle's metaphysics was the last grand attempt to systematize being. Instancology is the first attempt to systematize instancing. The shift is subtle but seismic: from what is to how it appears, from stable substance to dynamic issuance, from fixed essence to relational structure.


This is not merely a philosophical correction. It is a civilizational pivot. The rebirth of metaphysics is not an academic project—it is a cultural necessity. Without a structured metaphysical core, all knowledge—science, ethics, art, politics—will continue to orbit in relativistic drift.


Instancology offers a new axis. A reborn metaphysics, not nostalgic, but necessary. A path not back to Aristotle’s stronghold, but forward through a new portal—where being, knowing, and issuing are reconciled into one structured vision of reality.